Английская Википедия:Banach–Alaoglu theorem

Материал из Онлайн справочника
Перейти к навигацииПерейти к поиску

Шаблон:Short description In functional analysis and related branches of mathematics, the Banach–Alaoglu theorem (also known as Alaoglu's theorem) states that the closed unit ball of the dual space of a normed vector space is compact in the weak* topology.[1] A common proof identifies the unit ball with the weak-* topology as a closed subset of a product of compact sets with the product topology. As a consequence of Tychonoff's theorem, this product, and hence the unit ball within, is compact.

This theorem has applications in physics when one describes the set of states of an algebra of observables, namely that any state can be written as a convex linear combination of so-called pure states.

History

According to Lawrence Narici and Edward Beckenstein, the Alaoglu theorem is a “very important result—maybe Шаблон:Em most important fact about the weak-* topology—[that] echos throughout functional analysis.”Шаблон:Sfn In 1912, Helly proved that the unit ball of the continuous dual space of <math>C([a, b])</math> is countably weak-* compact.Шаблон:Sfn In 1932, Stefan Banach proved that the closed unit ball in the continuous dual space of any separable normed space is sequentially weak-* compact (Banach only considered sequential compactness).Шаблон:Sfn The proof for the general case was published in 1940 by the mathematician Leonidas Alaoglu. According to Pietsch [2007], there are at least twelve mathematicians who can lay claim to this theorem or an important predecessor to it.Шаблон:Sfn

The Bourbaki–Alaoglu theorem is a generalization[2][3] of the original theorem by Bourbaki to dual topologies on locally convex spaces. This theorem is also called the Banach–Alaoglu theorem or the weak-* compactness theorem and it is commonly called simply the Alaoglu theorem.Шаблон:Sfn

Statement

Шаблон:See also

If <math>X</math> is a vector space over the field <math>\mathbb{K}</math> then <math>X^{\#}</math> will denote the algebraic dual space of <math>X</math> and these two spaces are henceforth associated with the bilinear Шаблон:Em <math>\left\langle \cdot, \cdot \right\rangle : X \times X^{\#} \to \mathbb{K}</math> defined by <math display=block>\left\langle x, f \right\rangle ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ f(x)</math> where the triple <math>\left\langle X, X^{\#},\left\langle \cdot, \cdot \right\rangle \right\rangle</math> forms a dual system called the Шаблон:Em.

If <math>X</math> is a topological vector space (TVS) then its continuous dual space will be denoted by <math>X^{\prime},</math> where <math>X^{\prime} \subseteq X^{\#}</math> always holds. Denote the weak-* topology on <math>X^{\#}</math> by <math>\sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)</math> and denote the weak-* topology on <math>X^{\prime}</math> by <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right).</math> The weak-* topology is also called the topology of pointwise convergence because given a map <math>f</math> and a net of maps <math>f_{\bull} = \left(f_i\right)_{i \in I},</math> the net <math>f_{\bull}</math> converges to <math>f</math> in this topology if and only if for every point <math>x</math> in the domain, the net of values <math>\left(f_i(x)\right)_{i \in I}</math> converges to the value <math>f(x).</math>

Шаблон:Math theorem

Proof involving duality theory

Шаблон:Math proof |f(x)|\leq 1 \right\}</math> be the bipolar of <math>U</math> with respect to <math>\left\langle X, X^{\prime} \right\rangle</math>;

  • <math>U^{\#} = \left\{f \in X^{\#} ~:~ \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1\right\}</math> be the polar of <math>U</math> with respect to the canonical dual system <math>\left\langle X, X^{\#} \right\rangle.</math> Note that <math>U^{\circ} = U^{\#} \cap X^{\prime}.</math>

A well known fact about polar sets is that <math>U^{\circ\circ\circ} \subseteq U^{\circ}.</math>

  1. Show that <math>U^{\#}</math> is a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)</math>-closed subset of <math>X^{\#}:</math> Let <math>f \in X^{\#}</math> and suppose that <math>f_{\bull} = \left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> is a net in <math>U^{\#}</math> that converges to <math>f</math> in <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right).</math> To conclude that <math>f \in U^{\#},</math> it is sufficient (and necessary) to show that <math>|f(u)| \leq 1</math> for every <math>u \in U.</math> Because <math>f_i(u) \to f(u)</math> in the scalar field <math>\mathbb{K}</math> and every value <math>f_i(u)</math> belongs to the closed (in <math>\mathbb{K}</math>) subset <math>\left\{ s \in \mathbb{K} : |s| \leq 1 \right\},</math> so too must this net's limit <math>f(u)</math> belong to this set. Thus <math>|f(u)| \leq 1.</math>
  2. Show that <math>U^{\#} = U^{\circ}</math> and then conclude that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a closed subset of both <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right)</math> and <math>\left(X^{\prime}, \sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)\right):</math> The inclusion <math>U^{\circ} \subseteq U^{\#}</math> holds because every continuous linear functional is (in particular) a linear functional. For the reverse inclusion <math>\,U^{\#} \subseteq U^{\circ},\,</math> let <math>f \in U^{\#}</math> so that <math>\;\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1,\,</math> which states exactly that the linear functional <math>f</math> is bounded on the neighborhood <math>U</math>; thus <math>f</math> is a continuous linear functional (that is, <math>f \in X^{\prime}</math>) and so <math>f \in U^{\circ},</math> as desired. Using (1) and the fact that the intersection <math>U^{\#} \cap X^{\prime} = U^{\circ} \cap X^{\prime} = U^{\circ}</math> is closed in the subspace topology on <math>X^{\prime},</math> the claim about <math>U^{\circ}</math> being closed follows.
  3. Show that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-totally bounded subset of <math>X^{\prime}:</math> By the bipolar theorem, <math>U \subseteq U^{\circ\circ}</math> where because the neighborhood <math>U</math> is an absorbing subset of <math>X,</math> the same must be true of the set <math>U^{\circ\circ};</math> it is possible to prove that this implies that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-bounded subset of <math>X^{\prime}.</math> Because <math>X</math> distinguishes points of <math>X^{\prime},</math> a subset of <math>X^{\prime}</math> is <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-bounded if and only if it is <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-totally bounded. So in particular, <math>U^{\circ}</math> is also <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-totally bounded.
  4. Conclude that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is also a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)</math>-totally bounded subset of <math>X^{\#}:</math> Recall that the <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math> topology on <math>X^{\prime}</math> is identical to the subspace topology that <math>X^{\prime}</math> inherits from <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right).</math> This fact, together with (3) and the definition of "totally bounded", implies that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)</math>-totally bounded subset of <math>X^{\#}.</math>
  5. Finally, deduce that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a <math>\sigma\left(X^{\prime}, X\right)</math>-compact subset of <math>X^{\prime}:</math> Because <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right)</math> is a complete TVS and <math>U^{\circ}</math> is a closed (by (2)) and totally bounded (by (4)) subset of <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right),</math> it follows that <math>U^{\circ}</math> is compact. <math>\blacksquare</math>

}}

If <math>X</math> is a normed vector space, then the polar of a neighborhood is closed and norm-bounded in the dual space. In particular, if <math>U</math> is the open (or closed) unit ball in <math>X</math> then the polar of <math>U</math> is the closed unit ball in the continuous dual space <math>X^{\prime}</math> of <math>X</math> (with the usual dual norm). Consequently, this theorem can be specialized to:

Шаблон:Math theorem

When the continuous dual space <math>X^{\prime}</math> of <math>X</math> is an infinite dimensional normed space then it is Шаблон:Em for the closed unit ball in <math>X^{\prime}</math> to be a compact subset when <math>X^{\prime}</math> has its usual norm topology. This is because the unit ball in the norm topology is compact if and only if the space is finite-dimensional (cf. F. Riesz theorem). This theorem is one example of the utility of having different topologies on the same vector space.

It should be cautioned that despite appearances, the Banach–Alaoglu theorem does Шаблон:Em imply that the weak-* topology is locally compact. This is because the closed unit ball is only a neighborhood of the origin in the strong topology, but is usually not a neighborhood of the origin in the weak-* topology, as it has empty interior in the weak* topology, unless the space is finite-dimensional. In fact, it is a result of Weil that all locally compact Hausdorff topological vector spaces must be finite-dimensional.

Elementary proof

The following elementary proof does not utilize duality theory and requires only basic concepts from set theory, topology, and functional analysis. What is needed from topology is a working knowledge of net convergence in topological spaces and familiarity with the fact that a linear functional is continuous if and only if it is bounded on a neighborhood of the origin (see the articles on continuous linear functionals and sublinear functionals for details). Also required is a proper understanding of the technical details of how the space <math>\mathbb{K}^X</math> of all functions of the form <math>X \to \mathbb{K}</math> is identified as the Cartesian product <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K},</math> and the relationship between pointwise convergence, the product topology, and subspace topologies they induce on subsets such as the algebraic dual space <math>X^{\#}</math> and products of subspaces such as <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x}.</math> An explanation of these details is now given for readers who are interested.

Шаблон:Collapse top

For every real <math>r,</math> <math>B_r ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \{c \in \mathbb{K} : |c| \leq r\}</math> will denote the closed ball of radius <math>r</math> centered at <math>0</math> and <math>r U ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \{r u : u \in U\}</math> for any <math>U \subseteq X,</math>

Identification of functions with tuples

The Cartesian product <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> is usually thought of as the set of all <math>X</math>-indexed tuples <math>s_{\bull} = \left(s_x\right)_{x \in X}</math> but, since tuples are technically just functions from an indexing set, it can also be identified with the space <math>\mathbb{K}^X</math> of all functions having prototype <math>X \to \mathbb{K},</math> as is now described:

  • Шаблон:Em: A function <math>s : X \to \mathbb{K}</math> belonging to <math>\mathbb{K}^X</math> is identified with its (<math>X</math>-indexed) "Шаблон:Em" <math>s_{\bull} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ (s(x))_{x \in X}.</math>
  • Шаблон:Em: A tuple <math>s_{\bull} = \left(s_x\right)_{x \in X}</math> in <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> is identified with the function <math>s : X \to \mathbb{K}</math> defined by <math>s(x) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ s_x</math>; this function's "tuple of values" is the original tuple <math>\left(s_x\right)_{x \in X}.</math>

This is the reason why many authors write, often without comment, the equality <math display=block>\mathbb{K}^X = \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> and why the Cartesian product <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> is sometimes taken as the definition of the set of maps <math>\mathbb{K}^X</math> (or conversely). However, the Cartesian product, being the (categorical) product in the category of sets (which is a type of inverse limit), also comes equipped with associated maps that are known as its (coordinate) Шаблон:Em.

The Шаблон:Visible anchor at a given point <math>z \in X</math> is the function <math display=block>\Pr{}_z : \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} \to \mathbb{K} \quad \text{ defined by } \quad s_{\bull} = \left(s_x\right)_{x \in X} \mapsto s_z</math> where under the above identification, <math>\Pr{}_z</math> sends a function <math>s : X \to \mathbb{K}</math> to <math display=block>\Pr{}_z(s) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ s(z).</math> Stated in words, for a point <math>z</math> and function <math>s,</math> "plugging <math>z</math> into <math>s</math>" is the same as "plugging <math>s</math> into <math>\Pr{}_z</math>".

In particular, suppose that <math>\left(r_x\right)_{x \in X}</math> are non-negative real numbers. Then <math>\prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x} \subseteq \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} = \mathbb{K}^X,</math> where under the above identification of tuples with functions, <math>\prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x}</math> is the set of all functions <math>s \in \mathbb{K}^X</math> such that <math>s(x) \in B_{r_x}</math> for every <math>x \in X.</math>

If a subset <math>U \subseteq X</math> partitions <math>X</math> into <math>X = U \, \cup \,(X \setminus U)</math> then the linear bijection <math display=block>\begin{alignat}{4} H :\;&& \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} &&\;\to \;& \left(\prod_{u \in U} \mathbb{K}\right) \times \prod_{x \in X \setminus U} \mathbb{K} \\[0.3ex]

    && \left(f_x\right)_{x \in X} &&\;\mapsto\;& \left( \left(f_u\right)_{u \in U}, \; \left(f_x\right)_{x \in X \setminus U} \right) \\

\end{alignat}</math> canonically identifies these two Cartesian products; moreover, this map is a homeomorphism when these products are endowed with their product topologies. In terms of function spaces, this bijection could be expressed as <math display=block>\begin{alignat}{4} H :\;&& \mathbb{K}^X &&\;\to \;& \mathbb{K}^U \times \mathbb{K}^{X \setminus U} \\[0.3ex]

    && f &&\;\mapsto\;& \left(f\big\vert_U, \; f\big\vert_{X \setminus U}\right) \\

\end{alignat}.</math>

Notation for nets and function composition with nets

A net <math>x_{\bull} = \left(x_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> in <math>X</math> is by definition a function <math>x_{\bull} : I \to X</math> from a non-empty directed set <math>(I, \leq).</math> Every sequence in <math>X,</math> which by definition is just a function of the form <math>\N \to X,</math> is also a net. As with sequences, the value of a net <math>x_{\bull}</math> at an index <math>i \in I</math> is denoted by <math>x_i</math>; however, for this proof, this value <math>x_i</math> may also be denoted by the usual function parentheses notation <math>x_{\bull}(i).</math> Similarly for function composition, if <math>F : X \to Y</math> is any function then the net (or sequence) that results from "plugging <math>x_{\bull}</math> into <math>F</math>" is just the function <math>F \circ x_{\bull} : I \to Y,</math> although this is typically denoted by <math>\left(F\left(x_i\right)\right)_{i \in I}</math> (or by <math>\left(F\left(x_i\right)\right)_{i=1}^{\infty}</math> if <math>x_{\bull}</math> is a sequence). In the proofs below, this resulting net may be denoted by any of the following notations <math display=block>F\left(x_{\bull}\right) = \left(F\left(x_i\right)\right)_{i \in I} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ F \circ x_{\bull},</math> depending on whichever notation is cleanest or most clearly communicates the intended information. In particular, if <math>F : X \to Y</math> is continuous and <math>x_{\bull} \to x</math> in <math>X,</math> then the conclusion commonly written as <math>\left(F\left(x_i\right)\right)_{i \in I} \to F(x)</math> may instead be written as <math>F\left(x_{\bull}\right) \to F(x)</math> or <math>F \circ x_{\bull} \to F(x).</math>

Topology

The set <math display=inline>\mathbb{K}^X = \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> is assumed to be endowed with the product topology. It is well known that the product topology is identical to the topology of pointwise convergence. This is because given <math>f</math> and a net <math>\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I},</math> where <math>f</math> and every <math>f_i</math> is an element of <math display=inline>\mathbb{K}^X = \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K},</math> then the net <math>\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I} \to f</math> converges in the product topology if and only if

for every <math>z \in X,</math> the net <math>\Pr{}_z\left(\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}\right) \to \Pr{}_z(f)</math> converges in <math>\mathbb{K},</math>

where because <math>\;\Pr{}_z(f) = f(z)\;</math> and <math display=inline>\Pr{}_z\left(\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}\right) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left(\Pr{}_z\left(f_i\right)\right)_{i \in I} = \left(f_i(z)\right)_{i \in I},</math> this happens if and only if

for every <math>z \in X,</math> the net <math>\left(f_i(z)\right)_{i \in I} \to f(z)</math> converges in <math>\mathbb{K},</math>

Thus <math>\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> converges to <math>f</math> in the product topology if and only if it converges to <math>f</math> pointwise on <math>X.</math>

This proof will also use the fact that the topology of pointwise convergence is preserved when passing to topological subspaces. This means, for example, that if for every <math>x \in X,</math> <math>S_x \subseteq \mathbb{K}</math> is some (topological) subspace of <math>\mathbb{K}</math> then the topology of pointwise convergence (or equivalently, the product topology) on <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} S_x</math> is equal to the subspace topology that the set <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} S_x</math> inherits from <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}.</math> And if <math>S_x</math> is closed in <math>\mathbb{K}</math> for every <math>x \in X,</math> then <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} S_x</math> is a closed subset of <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}.</math>

Characterization of <math>\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq r</math>

An important fact used by the proof is that for any real <math>r,</math> <math display=block>\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq r \qquad \text{ if and only if } \qquad f(U) \subseteq B_r</math> where <math>\,\sup\,</math> denotes the supremum and <math>f(U) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \{f(u) : u \in U\}.</math> As a side note, this characterization does not hold if the closed ball <math>B_r</math> is replaced with the open ball <math>\{c \in \mathbb{K} : |c| < r\}</math> (and replacing <math>\;\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq r\;</math> with the strict inequality <math>\;\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| < r\;</math> will not change this; for counter-examples, consider <math>X ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \mathbb{K}</math> and the identity map <math>f ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \operatorname{Id}</math> on <math>X</math>). Шаблон:Collapse bottom

The essence of the Banach–Alaoglu theorem can be found in the next proposition, from which the Banach–Alaoglu theorem follows. Unlike the Banach–Alaoglu theorem, this proposition does Шаблон:Em require the vector space <math>X</math> to endowed with any topology.

Шаблон:Math theorem{=}~ \{s \in \mathbb{K} : |s| \leq r\}</math> with its usual topology (<math>X</math> need not be endowed with any topology, but <math>\mathbb{K}</math> has its usual Euclidean topology). Define <math display=block>U^{\#} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \Big\{f \in X^{\#} ~:~ \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1\Big\}.</math>

If for every <math>x \in X,</math> <math>r_x > 0</math> is a real number such that <math>x \in r_x U,</math> then <math>U^{\#}</math> is a closed and compact subspace of the product space <math>\prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x}</math> (where because this product topology is identical to the topology of pointwise convergence, which is also called the weak-* topology in functional analysis, this means that <math>U^{\#}</math> is compact in the weak-* topology or "weak-* compact" for short). }}

Before proving the proposition above, it is first shown how the Banach–Alaoglu theorem follows from it (unlike the proposition, Banach–Alaoglu assumes that <math>X</math> is a topological vector space (TVS) and that <math>U</math> is a neighborhood of the origin).

Шаблон:Math proof{=}~ \Big\{f \in X^{\prime} ~:~ \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1\Big\} ~=~ U^{\#} \cap X^{\prime}.</math>

Proof that <math>U^{\circ} = U^{\#}:</math> Because <math>U^{\circ} = U^{\#} \cap X^{\prime},</math> the conclusion is equivalent to <math>U^{\#} \subseteq X^{\prime}.</math> If <math>f \in U^{\#}</math> then <math>\;\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1,\,</math> which states exactly that the linear functional <math>f</math> is bounded on the neighborhood <math>U;</math> thus <math>f</math> is a continuous linear functional (that is, <math>f \in X^{\prime}</math>), as desired. <math>\blacksquare</math> }}

Шаблон:Math proof{=}~ \{s \in \mathbb{K} : |s| \leq r_x\}</math> is a Hausdorff[note 1] compact space). Because a closed subset of a compact space is compact, the proof of the proposition will be complete once it is shown that <math display=block>U^{\#} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \Big\{f \in X^{\#} ~:~ \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1\Big\} ~=~ \left\{f \in X^{\#} ~:~ f(U) \subseteq B_1\right\}</math> is a closed subset of <math display=inline>\prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x}.</math> The following statements guarantee this conclusion:

  1. <math>U^{\#} \subseteq \prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x}.</math>
  2. <math>U^{\#}</math> is a closed subset of the product space <math>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} = \mathbb{K}^X.</math>

Proof of (1):

For any <math>z \in X,</math> let <math display=inline>\Pr{}_z : \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} \to \mathbb{K}</math> denote the projection to the <math>z</math>th coordinate (as defined above). To prove that <math display=inline>U^{\#} \subseteq \prod_{x \in X} B_{r_x},</math> it is sufficient (and necessary) to show that <math>\Pr{}_x\left(U^{\#}\right) \subseteq B_{r_x}</math> for every <math>x \in X.</math> So fix <math>x \in X</math> and let <math>f \in U^{\#}.</math> Because <math>\Pr{}_x(f) \,=\, f(x),</math> it remains to show that <math>f(x) \in B_{r_x}.</math> Recall that <math>r_x > 0</math> was defined in the proposition's statement as being any positive real number that satisfies <math>x \in r_x U</math> (so for example, <math>r_u := 1</math> would be a valid choice for each <math>u \in U</math>), which implies <math>\,u_x ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \frac{1}{r_x} \, x \in U.\,</math> Because <math>f</math> is a positive homogeneous function that satisfies <math>\;\sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1,\,</math> <math display=block>\frac{1}{r_x}|f(x)| = \left|\frac{1}{r_x} f(x)\right| = \left|f\left(\frac{1}{r_x} x\right)\right| = \left|f\left(u_x\right)\right| \leq \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1.</math>

Thus <math>|f(x)| \leq r_x,</math> which shows that <math>f(x) \in B_{r_x},</math> as desired.

Proof of (2):

The algebraic dual space <math>X^{\#}</math> is always a closed subset of <math display=inline>\mathbb{K}^X = \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> (this is proved in the lemma below for readers who are not familiar with this result). The set <math display=block>\begin{alignat}{9} U_{B_1} &\,\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}\, \Big\{ ~~\;~~\;~~\;~~ f\ \in \mathbb{K}^X ~~\;~~ : \sup_{u \in U} |f(u)| \leq 1\Big\} \\ &= \big\{ ~~\;~~\;~~\;~~f \, \in \mathbb{K}^X ~~\;~~ : f(u) \in B_1 \text{ for all } u \in U\big\} \\ &= \Big\{\left(f_x\right)_{x \in X} \in \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} \,~:~ \; ~f_u~ \in B_1 \text{ for all } u \in U\Big\} \\ &= \prod_{x \in X} C_x \quad \text{ where } \quad C_x ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \begin{cases} B_1 & \text{ if } x \in U \\ \mathbb{K} & \text{ if } x \not\in U \\ \end{cases} \\ \end{alignat}</math> is closed in the product topology on <math>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K} = \mathbb{K}^X</math> since it is a product of closed subsets of <math>\mathbb{K}.</math> Thus <math>U_{B_1} \cap X^{\#} = U^{\#}</math> is an intersection of two closed subsets of <math>\mathbb{K}^X,</math> which proves (2).[note 2] <math>\blacksquare</math> }}

The conclusion that the set <math>U_{B_1} = \left\{f \in \mathbb{K}^X : f(U) \subseteq B_1\right\}</math> is closed can also be reached by applying the following more general result, this time proved using nets, to the special case <math>Y := \mathbb{K}</math> and <math>B := B_1.</math>

Observation: If <math>U \subseteq X</math> is any set and if <math>B \subseteq Y</math> is a closed subset of a topological space <math>Y,</math> then <math>U_B ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left\{f \in Y^X : f(U) \subseteq B\right\}</math> is a closed subset of <math>Y^X</math> in the topology of pointwise convergence.
Proof of observation: Let <math>f \in Y^X</math> and suppose that <math>\left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> is a net in <math>U_B</math> that converges pointwise to <math>f.</math> It remains to show that <math>f \in U_B,</math> which by definition means <math>f(U) \subseteq B.</math> For any <math>u \in U,</math> because <math>\left(f_i(u)\right)_{i \in I} \to f(u)</math> in <math>Y</math> and every value <math>f_i(u) \in f_i(U) \subseteq B</math> belongs to the closed (in <math>Y</math>) subset <math>B,</math> so too must this net's limit belong to this closed set; thus <math>f(u) \in B,</math> which completes the proof. <math>\blacksquare</math>

Шаблон:Math theorem

Шаблон:Collapse top Let <math>f \in \mathbb{K}^X</math> and suppose that <math>f_{\bull} = \left(f_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> is a net in <math>X^{\#}</math> the converges to <math>f</math> in <math>\mathbb{K}^X.</math> To conclude that <math>f \in X^{\#},</math> it must be shown that <math>f</math> is a linear functional. So let <math>s</math> be a scalar and let <math>x, y \in X.</math>

For any <math>z \in X,</math> let <math>f_{\bull}(z) : I \to \mathbb{K}</math> denote Шаблон:Em <math display=block>f_{\bull}(z) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left(f_i(z)\right)_{i \in I}.</math> Because <math>f_{\bull} \to f</math> in <math>\mathbb{K}^X,</math> which has the topology of pointwise convergence, <math>f_{\bull}(z) \to f(z)</math> in <math>\mathbb{K}</math> for every <math>z \in X.</math> By using <math>x, y, sx, \text{ and } x + y,</math> in place of <math>z,</math> it follows that each of the following nets of scalars converges in <math>\mathbb{K}:</math> <math display=block>f_{\bull}(x) \to f(x), \quad f_{\bull}(y) \to f(y), \quad f_{\bull}(x + y) \to f(x + y), \quad \text{ and } \quad f_{\bull}(sx) \to f(sx).</math>


Proof that <math>f(s x) = s f(x):</math> Let <math>M : \mathbb{K} \to \mathbb{K}</math> be the "multiplication by <math>s</math>" map defined by <math>M(c) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ s c.</math> Because <math>M</math> is continuous and <math>f_{\bull}(x) \to f(x)</math> in <math>\mathbb{K},</math> it follows that <math>M\left(f_{\bull}(x)\right) \to M(f(x))</math> where the right hand side is <math>M(f(x)) = s f(x)</math> and the left hand side is <math display=block>\begin{alignat}{4} M\left(f_{\bull}(x)\right) \stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}&~ M \circ f_{\bull}(x) && \text{ by definition of notation } \\ =&~ \left(M\left(f_i(x)\right)\right)_{i \in I} EducationBot (обсуждение) && \text{ because } f_{\bull}(x) = \left(f_i(x)\right)_{i \in I} : I \to \mathbb{K} \\ =&~ \left(s f_i(x)\right)_{i \in I} && M\left(f_i(x)\right) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ s f_i(x) \\ =&~ \left(f_i(s x)\right)_{i \in I} && \text{ by linearity of } f_i \\ =&~ f_{\bull}(sx) && \text{ notation } \end{alignat}</math> which proves that <math>f_{\bull}(sx) \to s f(x).</math> Because also <math>f_{\bull}(sx) \to f(sx)</math> and limits in <math>\mathbb{K}</math> are unique, it follows that <math>s f(x) = f(s x),</math> as desired.


Proof that <math>f(x + y) = f(x) + f(y):</math> Define a net <math>z_{\bull} = \left(z_i\right)_{i \in I} : I \to \mathbb{K} \times \mathbb{K}</math> by letting <math>z_i ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left(f_i(x), f_i(y)\right)</math> for every <math>i \in I.</math> Because <math>f_{\bull}(x) = \left(f_i(x)\right)_{i \in I} \to f(x)</math> and <math>f_{\bull}(y) = \left(f_i(y)\right)_{i \in I} \to f(y),</math> it follows that <math>z_{\bull} \to ( f(x), f(y) )</math> in <math>\mathbb{K} \times \mathbb{K}.</math> Let <math>A : \mathbb{K} \times \mathbb{K} \to \mathbb{K}</math> be the addition map defined by <math>A(x, y) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ x + y.</math> The continuity of <math>A</math> implies that <math>A\left(z_{\bull}\right) \to A(f(x), f(y))</math> in <math>\mathbb{K}</math> where the right hand side is <math>A(f(x), f(y)) = f(x) + f(y)</math> and the left hand side is <math display=block>A\left(z_{\bull}\right) ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ A \circ z_{\bull} = \left(A\left(z_i\right)\right)_{i \in I} = \left(A\left(f_i(x), f_i(y)\right)\right)_{i \in I} = \left(f_i(x) + f_i(y)\right)_{i \in I} = \left(f_i(x + y)\right)_{i \in I} = f_{\bull}(x + y) </math> which proves that <math>f_{\bull}(x + y) \to f(x) + f(y).</math> Because also <math>f_{\bull}(x + y) \to f(x + y),</math> it follows that <math>f(x + y) = f(x) + f(y),</math> as desired. <math>\blacksquare</math>

Шаблон:Collapse bottom

The lemma above actually also follows from its corollary below since <math>\prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}</math> is a Hausdorff complete uniform space and any subset of such a space (in particular <math>X^{\#}</math>) is closed if and only if it is complete.

Шаблон:Math theorem

Шаблон:Collapse top Because the underlying field <math>\mathbb{K}</math> is a complete Hausdorff locally convex topological vector space, the same is true of the product space <math display=inline>\mathbb{K}^X = \prod_{x \in X} \mathbb{K}.</math> A closed subset of a complete space is complete, so by the lemma, the space <math>\left(X^{\#}, \sigma\left(X^{\#}, X\right)\right)</math> is complete. <math>\blacksquare</math> Шаблон:Collapse bottom


The above elementary proof of the Banach–Alaoglu theorem actually shows that if <math>U \subseteq X</math> is any subset that satisfies <math>X = (0, \infty) U ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \{r u : r > 0, u \in U\}</math> (such as any absorbing subset of <math>X</math>), then <math>U^{\#} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left\{f \in X^{\#} : f(U) \subseteq B_1\right\}</math> is a weak-* compact subset of <math>X^{\#}.</math>

As a side note, with the help of the above elementary proof, it may be shown (see this footnote)[proof 1] that there exist <math>X</math>-indexed non-negative real numbers <math>m_{\bull} = \left(m_x\right)_{x \in X}</math> such that <math display=block>\begin{alignat}{4} U^{\circ} &= U^{\#} && \\ &= X^{\#} && \cap \prod_{x \in X} B_{m_x} \\ &= X^{\prime} && \cap \prod_{x \in X} B_{m_x} \\ \end{alignat}</math> where these real numbers <math>m_{\bull}</math> can also be chosen to be "minimal" in the following sense: using <math>P ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ U^{\circ}</math> (so <math>P = U^{\#}</math> as in the proof) and defining the notation <math>\prod B_{R_\bull} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \prod_{x \in X} B_{R_x}</math> for any <math>R_{\bull} = \left(R_x\right)_{x \in X} \in \R^X,</math> if <math display=block>T_P ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left\{R_{\bull} \in \R^X ~:~ P \subseteq \prod B_{R_\bull}\right\}</math> then <math>m_{\bull} \in T_P</math> and for every <math>x \in X,</math> <math>m_x = \inf \left\{ R_x : R_{\bull} \in T_P \right\},</math> which shows that these numbers <math>m_{\bull}</math> are unique; indeed, this infimum formula can be used to define them.

In fact, if <math>\operatorname{Box}_P</math> denotes the set of all such products of closed balls containing the polar set <math>P,</math> <math display=block>\operatorname{Box}_P ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left\{ \prod B_{R_\bull} ~:~ R_{\bull} \in T_P \right\} ~=~ \left\{ \prod B_{R_\bull} ~:~ P \subseteq \prod B_{R_\bull} \right\},</math> then <math display=inline>\prod B_{m_\bull} = \cap \operatorname{Box}_P \in \operatorname{Box}_P</math> where <math display=inline>\bigcap \operatorname{Box}_P</math> denotes the intersection of all sets belonging to <math>\operatorname{Box}_P.</math>

This implies (among other things[note 3]) that <math display=inline>\prod B_{m_\bull} = \prod_{x \in X} B_{m_x}</math> the unique least element of <math>\operatorname{Box}_P</math> with respect to <math>\,\subseteq;</math> this may be used as an alternative definition of this (necessarily convex and balanced) set. The function <math>m_{\bull} ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left(m_x\right)_{x \in X} : X \to [0, \infty)</math> is a seminorm and it is unchanged if <math>U</math> is replaced by the convex balanced hull of <math>U</math> (because <math>U^{\#} = [\operatorname{cobal} U]^{\#}</math>). Similarly, because <math>U^{\circ} = \left[\operatorname{cl}_X U\right]^{\circ},</math> <math>m_{\bull}</math> is also unchanged if <math>U</math> is replaced by its closure in <math>X.</math>

Sequential Banach–Alaoglu theorem

A special case of the Banach–Alaoglu theorem is the sequential version of the theorem, which asserts that the closed unit ball of the dual space of a separable normed vector space is sequentially compact in the weak-* topology. In fact, the weak* topology on the closed unit ball of the dual of a separable space is metrizable, and thus compactness and sequential compactness are equivalent.

Specifically, let <math>X</math> be a separable normed space and <math>B</math> the closed unit ball in <math>X^{\prime}.</math> Since <math>X</math> is separable, let <math>x_{\bull} = \left(x_n\right)_{n=1}^{\infty}</math> be a countable dense subset. Then the following defines a metric, where for any <math>x, y \in B</math> <math display=block>\rho(x,y) = \sum_{n=1}^\infty \, 2^{-n} \, \frac{\left|\langle x - y, x_n \rangle\right|}{1 + \left|\langle x - y, x_n \rangle\right|}</math> in which <math>\langle\cdot, \cdot\rangle</math> denotes the duality pairing of <math>X^{\prime}</math> with <math>X.</math> Sequential compactness of <math>B</math> in this metric can be shown by a diagonalization argument similar to the one employed in the proof of the Arzelà–Ascoli theorem.

Due to the constructive nature of its proof (as opposed to the general case, which is based on the axiom of choice), the sequential Banach–Alaoglu theorem is often used in the field of partial differential equations to construct solutions to PDE or variational problems. For instance, if one wants to minimize a functional <math>F : X^{\prime} \to \R</math> on the dual of a separable normed vector space <math>X,</math> one common strategy is to first construct a minimizing sequence <math>x_1, x_2, \ldots \in X^{\prime}</math> which approaches the infimum of <math>F,</math> use the sequential Banach–Alaoglu theorem to extract a subsequence that converges in the weak* topology to a limit <math>x,</math> and then establish that <math>x</math> is a minimizer of <math>F.</math> The last step often requires <math>F</math> to obey a (sequential) lower semi-continuity property in the weak* topology.

When <math>X^{\prime}</math> is the space of finite Radon measures on the real line (so that <math>X = C_0(\R)</math> is the space of continuous functions vanishing at infinity, by the Riesz representation theorem), the sequential Banach–Alaoglu theorem is equivalent to the Helly selection theorem.

Шаблон:Math proof

Consequences

Consequences for normed spaces

Assume that <math>X</math> is a normed space and endow its continuous dual space <math>X^{\prime}</math> with the usual dual norm.

  • The closed unit ball in <math>X^{\prime}</math> is weak-* compact.Шаблон:Sfn So if <math>X^{\prime}</math> is infinite dimensional then its closed unit ball is necessarily Шаблон:Em compact in the norm topology by F. Riesz's theorem (despite it being weak-* compact).
  • A Banach space is reflexive if and only if its closed unit ball is <math>\sigma\left(X, X^{\prime}\right)</math>-compact; this is known as James' theorem.Шаблон:Sfn
  • If <math>X</math> is a reflexive Banach space, then every bounded sequence in <math>X</math> has a weakly convergent subsequence. (This follows by applying the Banach–Alaoglu theorem to a weakly metrizable subspace of <math>X</math>; or, more succinctly, by applying the Eberlein–Šmulian theorem.) For example, suppose that <math>X</math> is the space Lp space <math>L^p(\mu)</math> where <math>1 < p < \infty</math> and let <math>q</math> satisfy <math>\frac{1}{p} + \frac{1}{q} = 1.</math> Let <math>f_1, f_2, \ldots</math> be a bounded sequence of functions in <math>X.</math> Then there exists a subsequence <math>\left(f_{n_k}\right)_{k=1}^{\infty}</math> and an <math>f \in X</math> such that <math display=block>\int f_{n_k} g\,d\mu \to \int f g\,d\mu \qquad \text{ for all } g \in L^q(\mu) = X^{\prime}.</math> The corresponding result for <math>p = 1</math> is not true, as <math>L^1(\mu)</math> is not reflexive.

Consequences for Hilbert spaces

  • In a Hilbert space, every bounded and closed set is weakly relatively compact, hence every bounded net has a weakly convergent subnet (Hilbert spaces are reflexive).
  • As norm-closed, convex sets are weakly closed (Hahn–Banach theorem), norm-closures of convex bounded sets in Hilbert spaces or reflexive Banach spaces are weakly compact.
  • Closed and bounded sets in <math>B(H)</math> are precompact with respect to the weak operator topology (the weak operator topology is weaker than the ultraweak topology which is in turn the weak-* topology with respect to the predual of <math>B(H),</math> the trace class operators). Hence bounded sequences of operators have a weak accumulation point. As a consequence, <math>B(H)</math> has the Heine–Borel property, if equipped with either the weak operator or the ultraweak topology.

Relation to the axiom of choice and other statements

Шаблон:See also

The Banach–Alaoglu may be proven by using Tychonoff's theorem, which under the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) axiomatic framework is equivalent to the axiom of choice. Most mainstream functional analysis relies on ZF + the axiom of choice, which is often denoted by ZFC. However, the theorem does Шаблон:Em rely upon the axiom of choice in the separable case (see above): in this case there actually exists a constructive proof. In the general case of an arbitrary normed space, the ultrafilter Lemma, which is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice and equivalent to Tychonoff's theorem for compact Шаблон:Em spaces, suffices for the proof of the Banach–Alaoglu theorem, and is in fact equivalent to it.

Шаблон:AnchorThe Banach–Alaoglu theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma, which implies the Hahn–Banach theorem for real vector spaces (HB) but is not equivalent to it (said differently, Banach–Alaoglu is also strictly stronger than HB). However, the Hahn–Banach theorem is equivalent to the following weak version of the Banach–Alaoglu theorem for normed space[4] in which the conclusion of compactness (in the weak-* topology of the closed unit ball of the dual space) is replaced with the conclusion of Шаблон:Em (also sometimes called Шаблон:Em);

Шаблон:Math theorem C</math> is not empty. }}

Compactness implies convex compactness because a topological space is compact if and only if every family of closed subsets having the finite intersection property (FIP) has non-empty intersection. The definition of convex compactness is similar to this characterization of compact spaces in terms of the FIP, except that it only involves those closed subsets that are also convex (rather than all closed subsets).

See also

Notes

Шаблон:Reflist

Proofs

Шаблон:Reflist

Citations

Шаблон:Reflist

References

Шаблон:Refbegin

Шаблон:Refend

Further reading

Шаблон:Duality and spaces of linear maps Шаблон:Functional analysis Шаблон:Topological vector spaces

  1. Шаблон:Harvnb, Theorem 3.15.
  2. Шаблон:Harvnb, Theorem (4) in §20.9.
  3. Шаблон:Harvnb, Theorem 23.5.
  4. Шаблон:Cite journal


Ошибка цитирования Для существующих тегов <ref> группы «note» не найдено соответствующего тега <references group="note"/>
Ошибка цитирования Для существующих тегов <ref> группы «proof» не найдено соответствующего тега <references group="proof"/>